Thinking Fast & Slow

Réussis tes devoirs et examens dès maintenant avec Quizwiz!

Heuristic #48: MISWANTING

(Daniel Gilbert's phrase). We exaggerate the effect of a significant purchase or changed circumstances on our future well-being. Things that are initially exciting eventually lose their appeal.

Heuristic #43: DURATION NEGLECT

Another corollary of the two selves: the duration of an unpleasant or pleasant experience doesn't seem to be as important as the memory of how painful or pleasurable the experience was.

Heuristic #47: THE FOCUSING ILLUSION

"Nothing in life is as important as it is when you are thinking about it," (page 402). This means when we're asked to evaluate a decision, life satisfaction, or preference we err if we focus on only one thing. How we answer, "What would make you happy?" depends on many factors and rarely is one factor determinant. Yet folks regularly focus on one issue—income, weather, health, relationships, pollution, etc.—and ignore other important factors. "How much pleasure do you get from your car?" Depends on how much you value the stereo, mileage, looks, age, cost, comfortable seats, tilt of steering wheel, etc. The fact is, our evaluations are often based on the heuristic that while we are thinking of a thing we generally think better of it, forgetting how infrequently we actually think about those things (income, weather, health, stereo, mileage, looks, etc). What initially strikes our fancy is absorbed into daily living, we adapt, we acclimate, we experience the initial pleasure less intensely as time progresses. "The remembering self is subject to a massive focusing illusion about the life that the experiencing self endures quite comfortably," (page 406).

Heuristic #27: THEORY-INDUCED BLINDNESS

"Once you have accepted a theory and used it as a tool in your thinking, it is extraordinarily difficult to notice its flaws. If you come upon an observation that does not seem to fit the model, you assume that there must be a perfectly good explanation that you are somehow missing," (page 277). When the blinders fall off the previously believed error seems absurd and the real breakthrough occurs when you can't remember why you didn't see the obvious. Potential for error: Clinging to old paradigms that have outlived their validity.

Heuristic #5: THE HALO EFFECT

"This is the tendency to like or dislike everything about a person—including things you have not observed," (page 82). The warm emotion we feel toward a person, place, or thing predisposes us to like everything about that person, place, or thing. Good first impressions tend to positively color later negative impressions and conversely, negative first impressions can negatively color later positive impressions. The first to speak their opinion in a meeting can "prime" others' opinions. A list of positive adjectives describing a person influences how we interpret negative Thinking Fast and Slow by Daniel Kahneman 4 Summarized by Erik Johnson adjectives that come later in the list. Likewise, negative adjectives listed early colors later positive adjectives. The problem with all these examples is that our intuitive judgments are impulsive, not clearly thought through, or critically examined. To remind System 1 to stay objective, to resist jumping to conclusions, and to enlist the evaluative skills of System 2, Kahneman coined the abbreviation, "WYSIATI," what you see is all there is. In other words, do not lean on information based on impressions or intuitions. Stay focused on the hard data before us. Combat over confidence by basing our beliefs not on subjective feelings but critical thinking. Increase clear thinking by giving doubt and ambiguity its day in court.

Heuristic #23: TRUSTING EXPERT INTUITION

"We are confident when the story we tell ourselves comes easily to mind, with no contradiction and no competing scenario. But ease and coherence do not guarantee that a belief held with confidence is true. The associative machine is set to suppress doubt and to evoke ideas and information that are compatible with the currently dominant story," (page 239). Kahneman is skeptical of experts because they often overlook what they do not know. Kahneman trusts experts when two conditions are met: the expert is in an environment that is sufficiently regular to be predictable and the expert has learned these regularities through prolonged practice. Potential for error: being mislead by "experts."

Heuristic #28: LOSS AVERSION

"You just like winning and dislike losing—and you almost certainly dislike losing more than you like winning," (page 281). System 1 thinking compares the psychological benefit of gain with the psychological cost of loss Thinking Fast and Slow by Daniel Kahneman 11 Summarized by Erik Johnson and the fear of loss usually wins. Potential for error: passing by a sure win in order to avoid what we think might be a possible loss even when the odds are in favor of winning.

Heuristic #44: NARRATIVE WHOLENESS

(my user friendly name). When we evaluate how well ours and others' lives have been lived we do well to consider the whole narrative and not just the end. But because of the previous three heuristics we are prone to devalue a long, sacrificial, generous life if at the end (or even after death) we discover episodes of selfishness, etc. "A story is about significant events and memorable moments, not about time passing. Duration neglect is normal in a story, and the ending often defines its character" (page 386). Potential for error: paying more attention to longevity than quality, making decisions based on how memorable it will be rather than how exciting and enriching the experience itself will be, and experiencing a moment of pleasure and forfeiting our reputation of integrity.

Heuristic #15: THE CONJUNCTION FALLACY

(violating the logic of probability). After hearing priming details about a made up person (Linda), people chose a plausible story over a probable story. Logically, it is more likely that a person will have one characteristic than two characteristics. That is, after reading a priming description of Linda respondents were more likely to give her two characteristics, which is statistically improbable. It is more likely Linda would be a bank teller (one characteristic) than a bank teller who is a feminist (two characteristics). "The notions of coherence, plausibility, and probability are easily confused by the unwary," (page 159). The more details we add to a description, forecast, or judgment the less likely they are to be probable. Why? Stage 1 thinking overlooks logic in favor of a plausible story. Potential for error: committing a logical fallacy, when our intuition favors what is plausible but improbable over what is implausible and probable.

Heuristic #29: THE ENDOWMENT EFFECT

An object we own and use is more valuable to us than an object we don't own and don't use. Such objects are endowed with significance and we're unwilling to part with them for two reasons: we hate loss and it has a history with us. Thus we won't sell a beloved, useful object unless a buyer offers significant payment. Objects we don't like or use sell for less (or we even give them away). Potential for error: Clinging to objects for sentimental reasons at considerable loss of income.

Heuristic #18: INTUITIVE PREDICTIONS

Conclusions we draw with strong intuition (System 1) feed overconfidence. Just because a thing "feels right" (intuitive) does not make it right. We need System 2 to slow down and examine our intuition, estimate baselines, consider regression to the mean, evaluate the quality of evidence, and so forth. "Extreme predictions and a willingness to predict rare events from weak evidence are both manifestations of System 1. It is natural for the associative machinery to match the extremeness of predictions to the perceived extremeness on which it is based—this is how substitution works," (page 194). Potential for error: unwarranted confidence when we are in fact in error.

Heuristic #1: PRIMING

Conscious and subconscious exposure to an idea "primes" us to think about an associated idea. If we've been talking about food we'll fill in the blank SO_P with a U but if we've been talking about cleanliness we'll fill in the blank SO_P with an A. Things outside of our conscious awareness can influence how we think. These subtle influences also affect behavior, "the ideomotor effect," (page 53). People reading about the elderly will unconsciously walk slower. And people who are asked to walk slower will more easily recognize words related to old age. People asked to smile find jokes funnier; people asked to frown find disturbing pictures more disturbing. It is true: if we behave in certain ways our thoughts and emotions will eventually catch up. We can not only feel our way into behavior, we can behave our way into feelings. Potential for error? We are not objective rational thinkers. Things influence our judgment, attitude, and behavior that we are not even aware of.

Heuristic #8: AFFECT

Emotions influence judgment. "People let their likes and dislikes determine their beliefs about the world," (page 103). Potential for error? We can let our emotional preferences cloud our judgment and either under or over estimate risks and benefits.

Heuristic #40: IGNORING FRAMES

How a problem is framed determines our choices more than purely rational considerations would imply. More drivers sign the "donate organ" card when they have to check the opt-in box, than drivers who must check the optout box. We are more willing to pay extra for gas when using a credit card (vs. cash) if the fee is framed as "loss of cash discount" than "added credit card surcharge." Doctors prefer interventions where outcomes are a "one month survival rate of 90%" than to interventions where outcomes are, "10% mortality rate." Both sentences mean the same thing statistically but the frame of "survival" has greater emotional value than "mortality rates." "The meaning of a sentence is what happens in your associative machinery while you understand it...In terms of the associations they bring to mind—how System 1 reacts to them—the two sentences really 'mean' different things," (page 363). "Reframing is effortful and System 2 is lazy," (page 367). Potential for error: Thinking we make decisions in an objective bubble when in fact there are subjective factors at work about which we are unaware.

Heuristic #42: THE PEAK END RULE

How an experience ends seems to hold greater weight in our memory than how an experience was lived. Similar to the previous heuristic, the peak end rule is shorthand for remembering only how an experience felt at its end not at this worst moment.

Heuristic #38: FEAR OF REGRET

Regret is an emotion we're familiar with and we do well to avoid making decisions that lead to regret. However, we're terrible at predicting how intense those feelings of regret will be. It often hurts less than we think.

Heuristic #19: THE NARRATIVE FALLACY

In our continuous attempt to make sense of the world we often create flawed explanatory stories of the past that shape our views of the world and expectations of the future. We assign larger roles to talent, stupidity, and intentions than to luck. "Our comforting conviction that the world makes sense rests on a secure foundation: our almost unlimited ability to ignore our ignorance," (page 201). This is most evident when we hear, "I knew that was going to happen!" Which leads to...

Heuristic #34: OVERESTIMATING THE LIKELIHOOD OF RARE EVENTS

It makes more sense to pay attention to things that are likely to happen (rain tomorrow) than about things that are unlikely to happen (terrorist attacks, asteroids, terminal illness, floods and landslides). We tend to overestimate the probabilities of unlikely events, and we tend to overweight the unlikely events in our decisions. This heuristic joins forces with the availability cascade (#13) and cognitive ease (#2) heuristics above. We are more likely to choose the alternative in a decision which is described with explicit vividness, repetition, and relative frequencies (vs. how likely). Potential for error: succumbing to fear mongers who manipulate data in favor of their cause.

Heuristic #35: THINKING NARROWLY

Most of us are so risk averse we avoid all gambles. This is wrong, says, Kahneman, since some gambles are clearly on our side and by avoiding them we lose money. One way to decrease risk aversion is to think broadly, looking at the aggregate wins over many small gambles. Thinking narrowly, looking only at short term losses, paralyzes us. But thinking broadly is non-intuitive. It's a System 2 task that takes work. We therefore are wired by System 1 to think irrationally economically (saying no to easy money). The limit of human rationality is so stark Kahneman calls it a "hopeless mirage" (page 335). The ideal of logical consistency is not achievable by our limited minds. Potential for error: passing by risks in our favor.

Heuristic #17: OVERLOOKING LUCK

Most people love to attach causal interpretations to the fluctuations of random processes. "It is a mathematically inevitable consequence of the fact that luck played a role in the outcome....Not a very satisfactory theory—we would all prefer a causal account—but that is all there is," (page 179). When we remove causal stories and consider mere statistics we'll observe regularities, what is called the regression to the mean. Those statistical regularities—regression to the mean—are explanations ("things tend to even out") but not causes ("that athlete had a bad day but is now 'hot'). "Our mind is strongly biased toward causal explanations and does not deal well with 'mere statistics,'" (page 182). Potential for error: seeing causes that don't exist.

Heuristic #9: THE LAW OF SMALL NUMBERS

Our brains have a difficult time with statistics. Small samples are more prone to extreme outcomes than large samples, but we tend to lend the outcomes of small samples more credence than statistics warrant. System 1 is impressed with the outcome of small samples but shouldn't be. Small samples are not representative of large samples. Large samples are more precise. We err when we intuit rather than compute, (see page 113). Potential for error? We make decisions on insufficient data.

Heuristic #32: THE CERTAINTY EFFECT

Outcomes that are almost certain are given less weight than their probability justifies. Think of lawyers who offer a "less than perfect" settlement before the trial which would result in an "almost certain victory."

Heuristic #30: LOSS AVERSION

People will work harder to avoid losses than to achieve gains. Golfers putt for par to avoid bogeys (loosing points for going over par) than for birdies (gaining points by putting under par). Contract negotiations stall when one party feels they're making more concessions (losses) than their disputant. People will work harder to avoid pain than to achieve pleasure. Even animals fight more fiercely to maintain territory than to increase territory. Potential for error: under estimating our own and other's attitudes toward loss/gain. They are asymmetrical.

Heuristic #14: REPRESENTATIVENESS

Similar to profiling or stereotyping, "representativeness" is the intuitive leap to make judgments based on how similar something is to something we like without taking into consideration other factors: probability (likelihood), statistics (base rate), or sampling sizes. Baseball scouts used to recruit players based on how close their appearance resembled other good players. Once players were recruited based on actual statistics the level of gamesmanship improved. Just because we like the design of a book cover doesn't mean we'll like the contents. You can't judge a book by its cover. A start-up restaurant has a low chance of survival regardless of how much you like their food. Many well run companies keep their facilities neat and tidy but a well kept lawn is no guarantee that the occupants inside are organized. To discipline our lazy intuition we must make judgments based on probability and base rates, and question our analysis of the evidence used to come up with our assumption in the first place. "Think like a statistician," (page 152). Potential for error: Evaluating a person, place, or thing on how much it resembles something else without taking into account other salient factors.

Heuristic #45: VALUING A REMEMBERING SELF OVER AN EXPERIENCING SELF

Since most of us rely on unreliable memories we do well to keep in mind what our experiences were like during them, not just at their conclusion. How many of our waking moments are spent in unpleasant emotions or negative states? They are hard to recall! "Our emotional state is largely determined by what we attend to, and we are normally focused on our current activity and immediate environment," (page 394). A person stuck in traffic can still be happy because they're in love, or a person who is grieving may still remain depressed while watching a comedy. Potential for error: not paying attention to what we are doing, letting experiences happen without reflection, and going with the flow with no attempt to alter our schedules, activities, or experiences.

Heuristic #6: JUDGEMENT

System 1 relies on its intuition, the basic assessments of what's going on inside and outside the mind. It is prone to ignore "sum-like variables," (page 93). We often fail to accurately calculate sums but rely instead on often unreliable intuitive averages. It is prone to "matching," (page 94). We automatically and subconsciously rate the relative merits of a thing by matching dissimilar traits. We are prone to evaluate a decision without distinguishing which variables are most important. This is called the "mental shotgun" approach (page 95). These basic assessments can easily replace the hard work System 2 must do to make judgments.

Heuristic #10: CONFIDENCE OVER DOUBT

System 1 suppresses ambiguity and doubt by constructing coherent stories from mere scraps of data. System 2 is our inner skeptic, weighing those stories, doubting them, and suspending judgment. But because disbelief requires lots of work System 2 sometimes fails to do its job and allows us to slide into certainty. We have a bias toward believing. Because our brains are pattern recognition devices we tend to attribute causality where none exists. Regularities occur at random. A coin flip of 50 heads in a row seems unnatural but if one were to flip a coin billions and billions of times the odds are that 50 heads in a row would eventually happen. "When we detect what appears to be a rule, we quickly reject the idea that the process is truly random," (page 115). Attributing oddities to chance takes work. It's easier to attribute them to some intelligent force in the universe. Kahneman advises, "accept the different outcomes were due to blind luck" (page 116). There are many facts in this world due to chance and do not lend themselves to explanations. Potential for error? Making connections where none exists.

Heuristic #33: THE EXPECTATION PRINCIPLE

The two heuristics above have this in common: "decision weights that people assign to outcomes are not identical to the probabilities of these outcomes, contrary to the expectation principle" (page 312). This means people attach values to gains and losses rather than wealth, and decision weights assigned to outcomes are different from probabilities. The fourfold pattern of preferences accounts for this. Potential for error: 1. People are risk averse when they look at the prospects of a large gain. They'll lock in a sure gain and accept a less than expected value of the gamble. 2. When the result is extremely large, such as a lottery ticket, the buyer is indifferent to the fact that their chance of winning is extremely small. Without the ticket they cannot win, but with the ticket, they can at least dream. 3. This explains why people buy insurance. We'll pay insurance because we're buying protection and peace of mind. 4. This explains why people take desperate gambles. They accept a high probability of just making things worse, for a chance of a slight ray of hope of avoiding the loss they are facing. This type of risk taking can just turn a bad situation into a disaster.

Heuristic #2: COGNITIVE EASE

Things that are easier to compute, more familiar, and easier to read seem more true than things that require hard thought, are novel, or are hard to see. "Predictable illusions inevitably occur if a judgment is based on the impression of cognitive ease or strain," (page 62). "How do you know that a statement is true? If it is strongly linked by logic or association to other beliefs or preferences you hold, or comes from a source you trust and like, you will feel a sense of cognitive ease," (page Thinking Fast and Slow by Daniel Kahneman 3 Summarized by Erik Johnson 64). Because things that are familiar seem more true teachers, advertisers, marketers, authoritarian tyrants, and even cult leaders repeat their message endlessly. Potential for error? If we hear a lie often enough we tend to believe it.

Heuristic #11: THE ANCHORING EFFECT

This is the subconscious phenomenon of making incorrect estimates due to previously heard quantities. If I say the number 10 and ask you to estimate Gandhi's age at death you'll give a lower number than if I'd said to you the number 65. People adjust the sound of their stereo volume according to previous "anchors," the parents' anchor is low decibels, the teenager's anchor is high decibels. People feel 35 mph is fast if they've been driving 10 mph but slow if they just got off the freeway doing 65 mph. Buying a house for $200k seems high if the asking price was raised from $180k but low if the asking price was lowered from $220k. A 15 minute wait to be served dinner in a restaurant seems long if the sign in the window says, "Dinner served in 10 minutes or less" but fast if the sign says, "There is a 30 minute wait before dinner will be served." Potential for error? We are more suggestible than we realize.

Heuristic #4: CONFIRMATION BIAS

This is the tendency to search for and find confirming evidence for a belief while overlooking counter examples. "Jumping to conclusions is efficient if the conclusions are likely to be correct and the costs of an occasional mistake acceptable, and if the jump saves much time and effort. Jumping to conclusions is risky when the situation is unfamiliar, the stakes are high, and there is no time to collect more information," (page 79). System 1 fills in ambiguity with automatic guesses and interpretations that fit our stories. It rarely considers other interpretations. When System 1 makes a mistake System 2 jumps in to slow us down and consider alternative explanations. "System 1 is gullible and biased to believe, System 2 is in charge of doubting and unbelieving, but System 2 is sometimes busy, and often lazy," (page 81). Potential for error? We are prone to over-estimate the probability of unlikely events (irrational fears) and accept uncritically every suggestion (credulity).

Heuristic #37: THE SUNK COST FALLACY

To avoid feeling bad about cutting our losses and being called a failure, we tend to throw good money after bad, stay too long in abusive marriages, and stay in unhappy careers. This is optimism gone hay-wire.

Heuristic #3: COHERENT STORIES (ASSOCIATIVE COHERENCE)

To make sense of the world we tell ourselves stories about what's going on. We make associations between events, circumstances, and regular occurrences. The more these events fit into our stories the more normal they seem. Things that don't occur as expected take us by surprise. To fit those surprises into our world we tell ourselves new stories to make them fit. We say, "Everything happens for a purpose," "God did it," "That person acted out of character," or "That was so weird it can't be random chance." Abnormalities, anomalies, and incongruities in daily living beg for coherent explanations. Often those explanations involve 1) assuming intention, "It was meant to happen," 2) causality, "They're homeless because they're lazy," or 3) interpreting providence, "There's a divine purpose in everything." "We are evidently ready from birth to have impressions of causality, which do not depend on reasoning about patterns of causation," (page 76). "Your mind is ready and even eager to identify agents, assign them personality traits and specific intentions, and view their actions as expressing individual propensities," (page 76). Potential for error? We posit intention and agency where none exists, we confuse causality with correlation, and we make more out of coincidences than is statistically warranted.

Heuristic #36: THE DISPOSITION EFFFECT

We are often willing to sell moneyearning stocks because it makes us feel like wise investors, and less willing to sell losing stocks because it's an admission of defeat. This is irrational since we'd earn more money by selling the losers and clinging to the winners.

Heuristic #25: THE OPTIMISTIC BIAS

We are prone to neglect facts, others' failures, and what we don't know in favor of what we know and how skilled we are. We believe the outcome of our achievements lies entirely in our own hands while neglecting the luck factor. We don't appreciate the uncertainty of our environment. We suffer from the Thinking Fast and Slow by Daniel Kahneman 10 Summarized by Erik Johnson illusion of control and neglect to look at the competition (in business start-ups for example). "Experts who acknowledge the full extent of their ignorance may expect to be replaced by more confident competitors, who are better able to gain the trust of clients," (page 263). Being unsure is a sign of weakness so we turn to confident experts who may be wrong. Potential for error: unwarranted optimism which doesn't calculate the odds and therefore could be risky.

Heuristic #41: IGNORING OUR TWO SELVES

We each have an "experiencing" self and a "remembering" self. The latter usually takes precedence over the former. That is, I can experience 13 days of vacation bliss but if on the 14th day things go bad I tend to remember the vacation as negative. My memory overrides my experience. Same with a 40 minute blissful record which ends with a scratch. We remember the scratch sound, not the 39 previous minutes of musical enjoyment. "Confusing experience with the memory of it is a compelling cognitive illusion—and it is the substitution that makes us believe a past experience can be ruined. The experiencing self does not have a voice," (page 381).

Heuristic #39: IGNORING JOINT EVALUATIONS

We make decisions differently when asked to make them in isolation than when asked to make them in comparison with other scenarios. For example, a victim in a robbery will be awarded a higher compensation when there are poignant factors involved (the victim was visiting a store he rarely visited), but will be awarded a lower compensation if harmed while in his usual shopping location. When locations are compared (joint evaluation) we realize the victim's location is insignificant and we reverse our original compensation amount. "Joint evaluations highlights a feature that was not noticeable in single evaluations but is recognized as a decisive when detected," (page 359). Potential for error: making decisions in isolation. We should do comparison shopping, compare sentences for crimes, and compare salaries for different jobs. Failure to do so limits our exposure to helpful norms.

Heuristic #26: OMITTING SUBJECTIVITY

We often think an object has only intrinsic objective value. A million dollars is worth a million dollars, right? Wrong. Magically making a poor person's portfolio worth a million dollars would be fabulous! Magically making a billionaire's portfolio a worth a million dollars would be agony! One gained, the other lost. Economists have erred by failing to consider a person's psychological state regarding value, risk, anxiety, or happiness. 18th century economist Bernoulli thought money had utility (fixed worth) but he failed to consider a person's reference point. Potential for error: Making decisions on pure logic without considering psychological states.

Heuristic #22: IGNORING ALGORITHMS

We overlook statistical information and favor our gut feelings. Not good! Forecasting, predicting the future of stocks, diseases, car accidents, and weather should not be influenced by intuition but they often are. And intuition is often wrong. We do well to consult check lists, statistics, and numerical records and not rely on subjective feelings, hunches, or intuition. Potential for error: "relying on intuitive judgments for important decisions if an algorithm is available that will make fewer mistakes," (page 229). Intuition means knowing something without knowing how we know it. Kahneman's understanding is that intuition is really a matter of recognition, being so familiar with something we arrive at judgments quickly. Chess players "see" the chess board, fire fighters "know" when a building is about to collapse, art dealers "identify" marks of forgeries, parents have a "sixth sense" when their kids are in danger, readers "read" letters and words quickly, and friends "are familiar" with their friends from a distance. Kids become experts at video games, motorists become expert drivers, and chefs become intuitive cooks. How? Recognition—either over long periods of exposure, or quickly in a highly emotional event (accidents). Intuition is immediate pattern recognition, not magic.

Heuristic #21: THE ILLUSION OF VALIDITY

We sometimes confidently believe our opinions, predictions, and points of view are valid when confidence is unwarranted. Some even cling with confidence to ideas in the face of counter evidence. "Subjective confidence in a judgment is not a reasoned evaluation of the probability that this judgment is correct. Confidence is a feeling, which reflects the coherence of the information and the cognitive ease of processing it" (page 212). Factors that contribute to overconfidence: being dazzled by one's own brilliance, affiliating with like-minded peers, and over valuing our track record of wins and ignoring our losses. Potential for error: Basing the validity of a judgment on the subjective experience of confidence rather than objective facts. Confidence is no measure of accuracy.

Heuristic #20: THE HINDSIGHT ILLUSION

We think we understand the past, which implies the future should be knowable, but in fact we understand the past less than we believe we do. Our intuitions and premonitions feel more true after the fact. Once an event takes place we forget what we believed prior to that event, before we changed our minds. Prior to 2008 financial pundits predicted a stock market crash but they did not know it. Knowing means showing something to be true. Prior to 2008 no one could show that a crash was true because it hadn't happened yet. But after it happened their hunches were retooled and become proofs. "The tendency to revise the history of one's beliefs in light of what actually happened produces a robust cognitive illusion," (page 203). Potential for error: "We are prone to blame decision makers for good decisions that worked out badly and to give them too little credit for successful moves that appear obvious only after the fact. When the outcomes are bad, the clients often blame their agents for not seeing the handwriting on the wall—forgetting that it was written in invisible ink that became legible only afterward. Actions that seemed prudent in foresight can look irresponsibly negligent in hindsight," (page 203).

Heuristic #12: THE AVAILABILITY HEURISTIC

When asked to estimate numbers like the frequency of divorces in Hollywood, the number of dangerous plants, or the number of deaths by plane crash, the ease with which we retrieve an answer influences the size of our answer. We're prone to give bigger answers to questions that are easier to retrieve. And answers are easier to retrieve when we have had an emotional personal experience. One who got mugged over-estimates the frequency of muggings, one exposed to news about school shootings over-estimates the number of gun crimes, and the one who does chores at home over estimates the percentage of the housework they do. When both parties assume they do 70% of the house work somebody is wrong because there's no such thing as 140%! A person who has experienced a tragedy will over estimate the potential for risk, danger, and a hostile universe. A person untroubled by suffering will under-estimate pending danger. When a friend gets cancer we get a check up. When nobody we know gets cancer we ignore the risk. Potential for error: under or over estimating the frequency of an event based on ease of retrieval rather than statistical calculation.

Heuristic #7: SUBSTITUTION

When confronted with a perplexing problem, question, or decision, we make life easier for ourselves by answering a substitute, simpler question. Instead of estimating the probability of a certain complex outcome we rely on an estimate of another, less complex outcome. Instead of grappling with the mind-bending philosophical question, "What is happiness?" we answer the easier question, "What is my mood right now?" (page 98). Even though highly anxious people activate System 2 often, obsessing and second guessing every decision, fear, or risk, it is surprising how often System 1 works just fine for them. Even chronic worriers function effortlessly in many areas of life while System 1 is running in the background. They walk, eat, sleep, breath, make choices, make judgments, trust, and engage in enterprises without fear, worry, or anxiety. Why? They replace vexing problems with easier problems. Potential for error? We never get around to answering the harder question.

Heuristic #16: OVERLOOKING STATISTICS

When given purely statistical data we generally make accurate inferences. But when given statistical data and an individual story that explains things we tend to go with the story rather than statistics. We favor stories with explanatory power over mere data. Potential for error: stereotyping, profiling, and making general inferences from particular cases rather than making particular inferences from general cases.

Heuristic #31: THE POSSIBILITY EFFECT

When highly unlikely outcomes are weighted disproportionately more than they deserve we commit the possibility effect heuristic. Think of buying lottery tickets.

Heuristic #13: AVAILABILITY CASCADES

When news stories pile up our statistical senses get warped. A recent plane crash makes us think air travel is more dangerous than car travel. The more we fear air travel the more eager news reporters are to sensationalize plane crashes. A negative feedback loop is set in motion, a cascade of fear. "The emotional tail wags the rational dog," (page 140). Potential for error? Over reacting to a minor problem simply because we hear a disproportionate number of negative news stories than positive ones.

Heuristic #46: AFFECTIVE FORECASTING

Which factor leads to a happier life duration: or experiences? Would a 20 year life with many happy experiences be better than a 60 year life with many terrible experiences? Which would you rather be: happy or old? We are terrible at predicting what will make us happy. When asked the very difficult question, "Overall, how happy is your life?" we substitute an easier question, "How happy am I right now?" (See heuristic #7). "...the responses to global well-being questions should be taken with a grain of salt" (page 399). People make decisions based on what will make them happy in the future but when it's achieved the happiness doesn't last. We don't know our future selves very well.

Heuristic #24: THE PLANNING FALACY

means taking on a risky project—litigation, war, opening a restaurant—confident of the best case scenario without seriously considering the worst case scenario. If we consult others who've engaged in similar projects we'll get the outside view. Failure to do this increases the potential for failure. Cost overruns, missed deadlines, loss of interest, waning urgency all result from poor planning. Potential for error: "making decisions based on delusional optimism rather than on a rational weight of gains, losses, and probabilities," (page 252). In other words, poorly planned grandiose projects will eventually fail.


Ensembles d'études connexes

Science 1096, 4th Edition, Self Test

View Set

Module 5 - Heart Disease & Cancer *still editing*

View Set

Chapter 2 of Computer Information systems stuff

View Set

Chapter 8 Terms AP World History

View Set

Micro-Economics Chapter 1 & 2 review

View Set

Chapter 31: Patients with Hypertension

View Set

Chapter 4- Civil Liberties- 1st Amendment

View Set

PVN 133 Growth & Development: Exam 1 & 2

View Set

Anatomy and Physiology Chapter 18: Nutrition and Metabolism

View Set