Logic Midterm 2
False Dichotomy
Fallacious presentation of two options as the only options where there are many
Red Herring
Fallacious subtle changing of topic to distract someone from noticing the weakness of your argument
Affirming the consequent and denying the antecedent are two example of a valid argument form
False
An indented indirect proof sequence must begin with an explicit contradiction have the form of p . ~p
False
Associativity applies only when a dot and a wedge appear within a statement
False
The explicit contradiction on the last indented line of an IP sequence may contain proposition letter that do not appear in the assumption line beginning the indented sequence
True
The expression (A>B) . C is logically equivalent to the expression C . (A>B)
True
Complex Question
Committed when two ( or more) questions are asked in the guise of a single question, and a single answer is given to both. The respondent's answer is added, an argument emerges that establishes the presumed condition
Begging the Question
Fallacious assumption of what you are trying to prove
Hasty Generalization
Fallacious generalization from a non-representative sample
Slippery Slope
Fallacious interference that if we accept something, we will be powerless to avoid future acts
Conjunction allows you to obtain the left-hand conjunct of a conjunctive proposition on a separate and subsequent line
False
Destructive Dilemma is an invalid argument form
False
If an argument is a substitution instance of an invalid argument form, then it must be an invalid argument
False
If an argument's conclusion contains a letter that does not appear in the argument's given premises, then the argument must be invalid
False
If you have a disjunction on its own line and the negation of the right-hand disjunct on another line, then you may use the disjunctive syllogism rule
False
In the application of the commutativity rule, the order of the letters remains unchanged, even though the placement of the parenthesis changes
False
It is impossible for a valid argument to be a substitution in stance of an invalid argument form
False
Modus Ponens is an Invalid argument form
False
Modus Tollens requires a conditional on its own line and the antecedent of that conditional on another line
False
One way to refute a constructive or destructive dilemma is to "grasp the dilemma by the horns,' which means to prove that the disjunctive premise is false
False
Rules of implication are rules of logical equivalence
False
Rules of replacement are applicable only to whole lines in a proof
False
Simplification allows you to obtain the right-hand conjunct of a conjunction on a separate and subsequent proof line
False
The assumption beginning an indirect proof sequence should be the same proposition you are trying to prove
False
The conditional proved by an indented conditional proof sequence should go on an indented line, within the scope of the assumption, immediately after the line containing the conditional's consequent
False
The distribution rule applies only to the conditional statement forms
False
The double negation rule states that any statement with the form p v q is logically equivalent to q v p
False
The indented line beginning a new conditional sequence should be justified by the acronym (CP)
False
The indirect proof method can be used to obtain the conclusion of an argument only if the argument is invalid
False
The last line of an indirect proof sequence must be an explicit contradiction of the form p>~p
False
The statment variables (p and q) in the form for DS can only stand for simple statements, not compound
False
To prove a biconditional using the conditional proof method, use two conditional proofs, one within the scope of the other
False
To prove a conditional with the conditional proof method, assume the conditional's consequent on an indented line, and derive the conditional's antecedent on a subsequent line within the scope of the indented sequence
False
To prove the conditional (C . I) > (Z v F) using the CP method, you should assume Z v F on an indented line and prove C . I w/n the scope of the indented sequence
False
When you are using a natural deduction proof to show that an argument is valid, the last line of your proof should always match the first premise
False
You can use constructive dilemma to prove a conjunction
False
You can use simplification to obtain any propositions letter from a previous compound proposition on separate and subsequent line
False
You do not need to discharge every indented Conditional or Indirect proof sequence to complete a proof correctly
False
Oversimplified Cause
Highlighting on aspect of the whole cause.
Gambler's Fallacy
In chance, thinking that there is a causal connection
Appeal to ignorance
The absence of evidence is not evidence of absence, the lack of proof for a claim is not evidence the claim is falce
Addition is the only rule of implication that allows you to introduce into a proof a new proposition letter that does not appear in the argument's given premises
True
Affirming the consequent is an invalid argument form
True
Any argument that is a substitution instance of a valid argument form is valid
True
Conditional proof can be used only to obtain a conditional with a horseshoe as its main operator
True
Destructive Dilemma is not included as an implication rule in your textbook's rules of implication
True
Disjunctive syllogism is a valid argument form
True
If an argument is a substitution instance of an invalid form, then it could still be a valid argument
True
If you are using a conditional proof sequence to prove a conditional whose consequent is also a conditional, then you can use another conditional proof sequence, within the scope of the original sequence, to obtain the conditional's consequent
True
If you are working within an indirect proof sequence within the scope of another indented sequence, then you can use lines from the outer sequence as justification for lines in the inner sequence
True
If you derive the statement ~R from the statement ~(ZvF)V~R and from the statement ~~(ZvF) then you are using disjunctive syllogism (DS)
True
If you have premises that are inconsistent, then you can use addition together with disjunctive syllogism to show that any proposition deductively follows
True
If you have the statement ~Z > F on one line and the statement ~Z on another line, then you can use the Modus Ponens rule
True
In a natural deduction proof, disjunctive syllogism always requires that you cite exactly two line numbers
True
In natural deduction proof using the first four implication rules, each new line must follow from the lines above by a rule
True
It is possible for a valid argument to a be a substitution of an invalid argument form in addition to being a substitution instance of a valid argument form
True
Modus Ponens requires a conditional ow its own line and the antecedent of that conditional on another line
True
Modus Tollens is a valid argument form
True
Once you have discharged an indented conditional proof sequence to obtain the resulting conditional, you can use the conditional as justification for the subsequent proof lines
True
One way to refute a constructive or destructive dilemma is to "grasp the dilemma by the horns," which means torueprove one or both of the conditionals in the first premise is false
True
Rules of replacement are not rules of implication
True
Rules of replacement may be applied to parts of an expression
True
Simplification requires that you cite only one previous line as justification for the new line
True
Sometimes you must perform the operation of double negation or the operation of commutativity on the statements in an argument to make the argument fit the pattern of a common argument form
True
The associativity rule states that the truth value of a conjunctive or disjunctive statement is unaffected by the placement of parenthesis when the same operator is used throughout
True
The axiom of replacement asserts that, within a proof logically equivalent expressions may replace each other
True
The conclusion (indicated by a single slash) indicates what the proof should yield in the end; therefore, you should not cite the conclusion line as justification for any lines within the actual proof
True
The last indented line of a conditional proof sequence should always be the consequent of the conditional you are trying to prove
True
The proposition Z v ~Z cannot serve as the last indented line of an indirect proof
True
The statement variables (p, q, and r) in the form of HS may stand for compound statements
True
The statement you conclude form an entire indirect sequence should be the negation of the assumption beginning the indented indirect proof sequence
True
When you are using conjunction to conjoin together with with a dot propositions on two previous proof lines, either propositions can become the left-hand conjunct
True
You can prove the validity of any valid argument using the indirect proof method
True
A conditional proof sequence should be indented to indicate that the indented lines are dependent upon the initial assumption beginning the sequence
True~
Post Hoc Ergo Propert Hoc
When things happen sequentially and assuming the first thing caused the second thing
Appeal to Unqualified Authority
When using an authority that is not related to the problem at hand
Non Causa Pro Causa
assuming causal relationship when there is none
IN a natural deduction proof, MP always requires that you cite exactly one line number
false