CSE261 Chapter1

Lakukan tugas rumah & ujian kamu dengan baik sekarang menggunakan Quizwiz!

Logic and bit operators

1 = true 0 = false

Propositional Satisfiability

A compound proposition is satisfiable if there is an assignment of truth values to its variables that makes it true. When no such assignments exist, the compound proposition is unsatisfiable -A compound proposition is unsatisfiable if and only if its negation is a tautology.

Consistent System Specifications

A list of propositions is consistent if it is possible to assign truth values to the proposition variables so that each proposition is true.

Translate the statement ∀x(C(x)∨ ∃y(C(y)∧F(x, y))) where C(x) is "x has a computer," and F(x,y) is "x and y are friends," and the domain for both x and y consists of all students in your school.

Every student in your school has a computer or has a friend who has a computer.

If R(x,y)= "x relies upon y" translate ∀x(∃y R(x,y))= ∃y(∀x R(x,y))= ∃x(∀y R(x,y))= ∀y(∃x R(x,y))=

Everyone has someone to rely on. There is a person whom everyone relies on including him/herself There is a person who relies on everyone Everyone relies upon everybody (including themselves)

Hypothesis and conclusion

In the conditional statement p → q, p is called the hypothesis (or antecedent or premise) and q is called the conclusion (or consequence).

tautology

Proposition which is always true. Example: p ∨¬p

Negating Quantified Expressions ∀x (De Morgan's Laws for Quantifiers)

Symbolically ¬∀x J(x) and ∃x ¬J(x) are equivalent "Every student in your class has taken a course in Java." Negating the original statement gives "It is not the case that every student in your class has taken Java." This implies that "There is a student in your class who has not taken Java."

Implication

The conditional statement p → q is the proposition "if p, then q." The conditional statement p → q is false when p is true and q is false, and true otherwise.

Converse

The proposition q → p is called the converse of p → q.

Inverse

The proposition ¬p → ¬q is called the inverse of p → q

Precedence of qualifiers

The quantifiers ∀ and ∃ have higher precedence than all the logical operators. For example, ∀x P(x) ∨ Q(x) means (∀x P(x)) ∨ Q(x)

Translate the statement ∃x∀y∀z((F(x,y)∧F(x,z)∧(y≠z))→¬F(y,z))

There is a student none of whose friends are also friends with each other.

Logically equivalent (p≡q)

Two compound propositions p and q are logically equivalent if p↔q is a tautology.

Contradiction

a proposition which is always false. Example: p ∧¬p

Arguments in Propositional Logic

an argument is a sequence of propositions, all but the final proposition are called premises; the last statement is the conclusion. the argument is valid if the premises imply the conclusion

Predicate logic (FOL: first-order logic)

distinguishes the subject of a sentence from its predicate. Variables: x, y, z Predicates: P(x), M(x) Quantifiers: used to express the meaning of English words including all and some

Proof by contraposition (indirect proof)

ex. proving p → q by assuming ¬q and show ¬p is true also. If we give a direct proof of ¬q → ¬p then we have a proof of p →q

Vacuous proof

if we know p is false then, p → q is true

trivial proof p → q

if we know q is true, then p → q is true as well

Identity Laws

p ^ T ≡ p p ∨ F ≡ p

Conditional statements and their contrapositive always have the same truth value (the inverse and converse are also equivalent)

p → q and ¬q → ¬p are equivalent

Distributive Laws

p ∧ (q ∨ r) ≡ (p ∧ q) ∨ (p ∧ r) p ∨ (q ∧ r) ≡ (p ∨ q) ∧ (p ∨ r)

Negation Laws

p ∨ ¬p ≡ T p ^ ¬p ≡ F

Double Negation Law

¬(¬p) ≡ p

Negation

¬p It is not the case that p

Disjunction

∨ p ∨ q "p or q." The disjunction p ∨ q is false when both p and q are false and is true otherwise.

Exclusive Or

⊕ p ⊕ q true when exactly one of p and q is true and is false otherwise.

Absorption Laws

p ∨ (p ∧ q) ≡ p p ∧ (p ∨ q) ≡ p

Domination Laws

p ∨ T ≡ T p ^ F ≡ F

Idempotent Laws

p ∨ p ≡ p p ^ p ≡ p

Conditional statements are true if the conclusion is true, regardless of the hypothesis

"If Juan has a smartphone, then 2 + 3 = 5" is true from the definition of a conditional statement, because its conclusion is true. (The truth value of the hypothesis does not matter then.)

Universal Quantifier

"for all" symbol: ∀ ∀x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for every x in the domain. ∀x P(x) is read as "For all x, P(x)" or "For every x, P(x)

Terminology used to express p → q

"if p, then q" "p is sufficient for q" "q if p" "q when p" "a necessary condition for p is q" "q unless ¬p" "p implies q" "p only if q" "a sufficient condition for q is p" "q whenever p" "q is necessary for p" "q follows from p"

Terminology used to express p ↔ q

"p is necessary and sufficient for q" "if p then q, and conversely" "p iff q."

Fallacy of denying the hypothesis

"p→q is true, and p is false, so q must be false." (No, because F→T is true.) a.k.a ((p→q)∧¬p) →¬q

Fallacy of affirming the conclusion

"p→q is true, and q is true, so p must be true." (No, because F→T is true.) a.k.a ((p→q)∧q)→p

Existential Quantifier

"there exists" symbol: ∃ ∃x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for some x in the domain. ∃x P(x) is read as "For some x, P(x)", or as "There is an x such that P(x)," or "For at least one x, P(x)."

Associative Laws

(p ∧ q) ∧ r ≡ p ∧ (q ∧ r) (p ∨ q) ∨ r ≡ p ∨ (q ∨ r)

Implication Law

(p→q)⇔(¬p∨q)

Number of rows in a truth table with n propositional variables

2^n

Conjunction

p ∧ q, "p and q." "p but q" The conjunction p ∧ q is true when both p and q are true and is false otherwise.

Negating Quantified Expressions ∃x (De Morgan's Laws for Quantifiers)

Symbolically ¬∃ x J(x) and ∀ x ¬J(x) are equivalent "There is a student in this class who has taken a course in Java." Negating the original statement gives "It is not the case that there is a student in this class who has taken Java." This implies that "Every student in this class has not taken Java"

Biconditional

The biconditional statement p ↔ q is the proposition "p if and only if q." The biconditional statement p ↔ q is true when p and q have the same truth values, and is false otherwise. Biconditional statements are also called bi-implications.

argument form

an argument that is valid no matter what propositions are substituted into its propositional variables. In an argument form, if the premises are p1,p2,...,pn and the conclusion is q then (p1 ∧p2 ∧ ...∧pn ) → q is a tautology.

Contrapositive

contrapositive of p → q is the proposition ¬q → ¬p

Commutative Laws

p ∧ q ≡ q ∧ p p ∨ q ≡ q ∨ p

De Morgan's Laws

¬(p ∧ q) ≡ ¬p ∨ ¬q ¬(p ∨ q) ≡ ¬p ∧ ¬q

"Every mail message larger than one megabyte will be compressed." Let L(m, y) be "Mail message m is larger than y megabytes." Let C(m) denote "Mail message m will be compressed."

∀m(L(m,1) → C(m))

Shorthand

∀x>0 P(x) is shorthand for "For all x that are greater than zero, P(x)." =∀x (x>0 → P(x)) ∃x>0 P(x) is shorthand for "There is an x greater than zero such that P(x)." =∃x (x>0 ∧ P(x))

Uniqueness Quantifier

∃!x P(x) means that P(x) is true for one and only one x in the universe of discourse (i.e. domain) "There is a unique x such that P(x)." "There is one and only one x such that P(x)"

"If a user is active, at least one network link will be available." Let A(u) represent "User u is active." Let S(n, x) represent "Network link n is in state x."

∃u A(u) →∃nS(n, available)


Set pelajaran terkait

Social Responsibilities and Ethics - Ch 11

View Set

200 hour Yoga Teacher Training Final

View Set

BANA 2372 - Chapter 4 - Midterm Exam 1 - Practice

View Set

Slopes of Parallel and Perpendicular Lines

View Set

FINAL Mod 6 - Stroke (PRACTICE QUESTIONS)

View Set

Chapter 10: the Economics of Banking

View Set

International Marketing & Sales Management

View Set