Relativity: The Special and General Theory, Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity

Pataasin ang iyong marka sa homework at exams ngayon gamit ang Quizwiz!

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.4 (a) We imagine the rigid body, to which the place specification is referred, supplemented in such a manner that the object whose position we require is reached by. the completed rigid body.

(b) In locating the position of the object, we make use of a number (here the length of the pole measured with the measuring-rod) instead of designated points of reference. (c) We speak of the height of the cloud even when the pole which reaches the cloud has not been erected. By means of optical observations of the cloud from different positions on the ground, and taking into account the properties of the propagation of light, we determine the length of the pole we should have required in order to reach the cloud.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XII: The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion 1.12.4

A priori it is quite clear that we must be able to learn something about the physical behaviour of measuring-rods and clocks from the equations of transformation, for the magnitudes z, y, x, t, are nothing more nor less than the results of measurements obtainable by means of measuring-rods and clocks. If we had based our considerations on the Galileian transformation we should not have obtained a contraction of the rod as a consequence of its motion.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XI: The Lorentz Transformation 1.11.6 Aided by the following illustration, we can readily see that, in accordance with the Lorentz transformation, the law of the transmission of light in vacuo is satisfied both for the reference-body K and for the reference-body K1. A light-signal is sent along the positive x-axis, and this light-stimulus advances in accordance with the equation x = ct, i.e. with the velocity c.

According to the equations of the Lorentz transformation, this simple relation between x and t involves a relation between x1 and t1. In point of fact, if we substitute for x the value ct in the first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation, we obtain: x'=(x-v)t/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) t'=(1-v/c)t/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) from which, by division, the expression x1 = ct1 immediately follows. If referred to the system K1, the propagation of light takes place according to this equation. We thus see that the velocity of transmission relative to the reference-body K1 is also equal to c. The same result is obtained for rays of light advancing in any other direction whatsoever. Of cause this is not surprising, since the equations of the Lorentz transformation were derived conformably to this point of view.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VII: The Apparent Incompatibility of the Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity 1.07.6 At this juncture the theory of relativity entered the arena.

As a result of an analysis of the physical conceptions of time and space, it became evident that in reality there is not the least incompatibility between the principle of relativity and the law of propagation of light, and that by systematically holding fast to both these laws a logically rigid theory could be arrived at. This theory has been called the special theory of relativity to distinguish it from the extended theory, with which we shall deal later. In the following pages we shall present the fundamental ideas of the special theory of relativity.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XII: The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion 1.12.6

As judged from K, the clock is moving with the velocity v; as judged from this reference- body, the time which elapses between two strokes of the clock is not one second, but 1/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) seconds, i.e. a somewhat larger time. As a consequence of its motion the clock goes more slowly than when at rest. Here also the velocity c plays the part of an unattainable limiting velocity.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VII: The Apparent Incompatibility of the Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity 1.07.1 There is hardly a simpler law in physics than that according to which light is propagated in empty space. Every child at school knows, or believes he knows, that this propagation takes place in straight lines with a velocity c= 300,000 km./sec.

At all events we know with great exactness that this velocity is the same for all colours, because if this were not the case, the minimum of emission would not be observed simultaneously for different colours during the eclipse of a fixed star by its dark neighbour. By means of similar considerations based on observations of double stars, the Dutch astronomer De Sitter was also able to show that the velocity of propagation of light cannot depend on the velocity of motion of the body emitting the light. The assumption that this velocity of propagation is dependent on the direction "in space" is in itself improbable.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section V: The Principle of Relativity (in the restricted sense) 1.05.3 As long as one was convinced that all natural phenomena were capable of representation with the help of classical mechanics, there was no need to doubt the validity of this principle of relativity.

But in view of the more recent development of electrodynamics and optics it became more and more evident that classical mechanics affords an insufficient foundation for the physical description of all natural phenomena. At this juncture the question of the validity of the principle of relativity became ripe for discussion, and it did not appear impossible that the answer to this question might be in the negative.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.3 This primitive method of place specification deals only with places on the surface of rigid bodies, and is dependent on the existence of points on this surface which are distinguishable from each other.

But we can free ourselves from both of these limitations without altering the nature of our specification of position. If, for instance, a cloud is hovering over Potsdamer Platz, then we can determine its position relative to the surface of the earth by erecting a pole perpendicularly on the Square, so that it reaches the cloud. The length of the pole measured with the standard measuring-rod, combined with the specification of the position of the foot of the pole, supplies us with a complete place specification. On the basis of this illustration, we are able to see the manner in which a refinement of the conception of position has been developed.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section V: The Principle of Relativity (in the restricted sense) 1.05.4 Nevertheless, there are two general facts which at the outset speak very much in favour of the validity of the principle of relativity.

Even though classical mechanics does not supply us with a sufficiently broad basis for the theoretical presentation of all physical phenomena, still we must grant it a considerable measure of "truth," since it supplies us with the actual motions of the heavenly bodies with a delicacy of detail little short of wonderful. The principle of relativity must therefore apply with great accuracy in the domain of mechanics. But that a principle of such broad generality should hold with such exactness in one domain of phenomena, and yet should be invalid for another, is a priori not very probable.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.2

Every description of the scene of an event or of the position of an object in space is based on the specification of the point on a rigid body (body of reference) with which that event or object coincides. This applies not only to scientific description, but also to everyday life. If I analyse the place specification "Potsdamer Platz, Berlin," I arrive at the following result. The earth is the rigid body to which the specification of place refers; "Potsdamer Platz, Berlin," is a well-defined point, to which a name has been assigned, and with which the event coincides in space.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.1 On the basis of the physical interpretation of distance which has been indicated, we are also in a position to establish the distance between two points on a rigid body by means of measurements.

For this purpose we require a "distance" (rod S) which is to be used once and for all, and which we employ as a standard measure. If, now, A and B are two points on a rigid body, we can construct the line joining them according to the rules of geometry; then, starting from A, we can mark off the distance S time after time until we reach B. The number of these operations required is the numerical measure of the distance AB. This is the basis of all measurement of length.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VII: The Apparent Incompatibility of the Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity 1.07.4 But this result comes into conflict with the principle of relativity set forth in Section V.

For, like every other general law of nature, the law of the transmission of light in vacuo [in vacuum] must, according to the principle of relativity, be the same for the railway carriage as reference-body as when the rails are the body of reference. But, from our above consideration, this would appear to be impossible. If every ray of light is propagated relative to the embankment with the velocity c, then for this reason it would appear that another law of propagation of light must necessarily hold with respect to the carriage — a result contradictory to the principle of relativity.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section I: Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions 1.01.4

If, in pursuance of our habit of thought, we now supplement the propositions of Euclidean geometry by the single proposition that two points on a practically rigid body always correspond to the same distance (line-interval), independently of any changes in position to which we may subject the body, the propositions of Euclidean geometry then resolve themselves into propositions on the possible relative position of practically rigid bodies. Geometry which has been supplemented in this way is then to be treated as a branch of physics. We can now legitimately ask as to the "truth" of geometrical propositions interpreted in this way, since we are justified in asking whether these propositions are satisfied for those real things we have associated with the geometrical ideas. In less exact terms we can express this by saying that by the "truth" of a geometrical proposition in this sense we understand its validity for a construction with rule and compasses.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XII: The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion 1.12.3

If, on the contrary, we had considered a metre-rod at rest in the x-axis with respect to K, then we should have found that the length of the rod as judged from K1 would have been sqrt(1-v^2/c^2); this is quite in accordance with the principle of relativity which forms the basis of our considerations.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.7

In practice, the rigid surfaces which constitute the system of co-ordinates are generally not available; furthermore, the magnitudes of the co-ordinates are not actually determined by constructions with rigid rods, but by indirect means. If the results of physics and astronomy are to maintain their clearness, the physical meaning of specifications of position must always be sought in accordance with the above considerations.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VII: The Apparent Incompatibility of the Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity 1.07.2

In short, let us assume that the simple law of the constancy of the velocity of light c (in vacuum) is justifiably believed by the child at school. Who would imagine that this simple law has plunged the conscientiously thoughtful physicist into the greatest intellectual difficulties? Let us consider how these difficulties arise.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section IX: The Relativity of Simultaneity 1.09.4 We were led to that conflict by the considerations of Section 6, which are now no longer tenable.

In that section we concluded that the man in the carriage, who traverses the distance w per second relative to the carriage, traverses the same distance also with respect to the embankment in each second of time. But, according to the foregoing considerations, the time required by a particular occurrence with respect to the carriage must not be considered equal to the duration of the same occurrence as judged from the embankment (as reference-body). Hence it cannot be contended that the man in walking travels the distance w relative to the railway line in a time which is equal to one second as judged from the embankment.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section I: Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions 1.01.1

In your schooldays most of you who read this book made acquaintance with the noble building of Euclid's geometry, and you remember — perhaps with more respect than love — the magnificent structure, on the lofty staircase of which you were chased about for uncounted hours by conscientious teachers. By reason of our past experience, you would certainly regard everyone with disdain who should pronounce even the most out-of-the-way proposition of this science to be untrue. But perhaps this feeling of proud certainty would leave you immediately if some one were to ask you: "What, then, do you mean by the assertion that these propositions are true?" Let us proceed to give this question a little consideration.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VIII: On the Idea of Time in Physics 1.08.7 This stipulation contains a further physical hypothesis, the validity of which will hardly be doubted without empirical evidence to the contrary.

It has been assumed that all these clocks go at the same rate if they are of identical construction. Stated more exactly: When two clocks arranged at rest in different places of a reference-body are set in such a manner that a particular position of the pointers of the one clock is simultaneous (in the above sense) with the same position, of the pointers of the other clock, then identical "settings" are always simultaneous (in the sense of the above definition).

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VIII: On the Idea of Time in Physics 1.08.1

Lightning has struck the rails on our railway embankment at two places A and B far distant from each other. I make the additional assertion that these two lightning flashes occurred simultaneously. If I ask you whether there is sense in this statement, you will answer my question with a decided "Yes." But if I now approach you with the request to explain to me the sense of the statement more precisely, you find after some consideration that the answer to this question is not so easy as it appears at first sight.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section IX: The Relativity of Simultaneity 1.09.5

Moreover, the considerations of Section 6 are based on yet a second assumption, which, in the light of a strict consideration, appears to be arbitrary, although it was always tacitly made even before the introduction of the theory of relativity.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section IX: The Relativity of Simultaneity 1.09.3

Now before the advent of the theory of relativity it had always tacitly been assumed in physics that the statement of time had an absolute significance, i.e. that it is independent of the state of motion of the body of reference. But we have just seen that this assumption is incompatible with the most natural definition of simultaneity; if we discard this assumption, then the conflict between the law of the propagation of light in vacuo and the principle of relativity (developed in Section 7) disappears.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section I: Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions 1.01.5

Of course the conviction of the "truth" of geometrical propositions in this sense is founded exclusively on rather incomplete experience. For the present we shall assume the "truth" of the geometrical propositions, then at a later stage (in the general theory of relativity) we shall see that this "truth" is limited, and we shall consider the extent of its limitation.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XII: The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion 1.12.2

Of course this feature of the velocity c as a limiting velocity also clearly follows from the equations of the Lorentz transformation, for these became meaningless if we choose values of v greater than c.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section IX: The Relativity of Simultaneity 1.09.1 Up to now our considerations have been referred to a particular body of reference, which we have styled a "railway embankment." We suppose a very long train travelling along the rails with the constant velocity v and in the direction indicated in Fig 1.

People travelling in this train will with a vantage view the train as a rigid reference-body (co-ordinate system); they regard all events in reference to the train. Then every event which takes place along the line also takes place at a particular point of the train. Also the definition of simultaneity can be given relative to the train in exactly the same way as with respect to the embankment. As a natural consequence, however, the following question arises: Are two events (e.g. the two strokes of lightning A and B) which are simultaneous with reference to the railway embankment also simultaneous relatively to the train? We shall show directly that the answer must be in the negative.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.6 This consists of three plane surfaces perpendicular to each other and rigidly attached to a rigid body.

Referred to a system of co-ordinates, the scene of any event will be determined (for the main part) by the specification of the lengths of the three perpendiculars or co-ordinates (x, y, z) which can be dropped from the scene of the event to those three plane surfaces. The lengths of these three perpendiculars can be determined by a series of manipulations with rigid measuring-rods performed according to the rules and methods laid down by Euclidean geometry.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section III: Space and Time in Classical Mechanics 1.03.3 In order to have a complete description of the motion, we must specify how the body alters its position with time; i.e. for every point on the trajectory it must be stated at what time the body is situated there.

These data must be supplemented by such a definition of time that, in virtue of this definition, these time-values can be regarded essentially as magnitudes (results of measurements) capable of observation. If we take our stand on the ground of classical mechanics, we can satisfy this requirement for our illustration in the following manner. We imagine two clocks of identical construction; the man at the railway-carriage window is holding one of them, and the man on the footpath the other. Each of the observers determines the position on his own reference-body occupied by the stone at each tick of the clock he is holding in his hand. In this connection we have not taken account of the inaccuracy involved by the finiteness of the velocity of propagation of light. With this and with a second difficulty prevailing here we shall have to deal in detail later.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XI: The Lorentz Transformation 1.11.2 If we drop these hypotheses, then the dilemma of Section 7 disappears, because the theorem of the addition of velocities derived in Section 6 becomes invalid. The possibility presents itself that the law of the propagation of light in vacuo may be compatible with the principle of relativity, and the question arises: How have we to modify the considerations of Section 6 in order to remove the apparent disagreement between these two fundamental results of experience?

This question leads to a general one. In the discussion of Section 6 we have to do with places and times relative both to the train and to the embankment. How are we to find the place and time of an event in relation to the train, when we know the place and time of the event with respect to the railway embankment? Is there a thinkable answer to this question of such a nature that the law of transmission of light in vacuo does not contradict the principle of relativity? In other words: Can we conceive of a relation between place and time of the individual events relative to both reference-bodies, such that every ray of light possesses the velocity of transmission c relative to the embankment and relative to the train? This question leads to a quite definite positive answer, and to a perfectly definite transformation law for the space-time magnitudes of an event when changing over from one body of reference to another.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section X: On the Relativity of the Conception of Distance 1.10.3 A priori it is by no means certain that this last measurement will supply us with the same result as the first.

Thus the length of the train as measured from the embankment may be different from that obtained by measuring in the train itself. This circumstance leads us to a second objection which must be raised against the apparently obvious consideration of Section 6. Namely, if the man in the carriage covers the distance w in a unit of time — measured from the train, — then this distance — as measured from the embankment — is not necessarily also equal to w.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section V: The Principle of Relativity (in the restricted sense) 1.05.2

We advance a step farther in our generalisation when we express the tenet thus: If, relative to K, K1 is a uniformly moving co-ordinate system devoid of rotation, then natural phenomena run their course with respect to K1 according to exactly the same general laws as with respect to K. This statement is called the principle of relativity (in the restricted sense).

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section X: On the Relativity of the Conception of Distance 1.10.1 Let us consider two particular points on the train travelling along the embankment with the velocity v, and inquire as to their distance apart.

We already know that it is necessary to have a body of reference for the measurement of a distance, with respect to which body the distance can be measured up. It is the simplest plan to use the train itself as reference-body (co-ordinate system). An observer in the train measures the interval by marking off his measuring-rod in a straight line (e.g. along the floor of the carriage) as many times as is necessary to take him from the one marked point to the other. Then the number which tells us how often the rod has to be laid down is the required distance.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VIII: On the Idea of Time in Physics 1.08.6 It is clear that this definition can be used to give an exact meaning not only to two events, but to as many events as we care to choose, and independently of the positions of the scenes of the events with respect to the body of reference (here the railway embankment).

We are thus led also to a definition of "time" in physics. For this purpose we suppose that clocks of identical construction are placed at the points A, B and C of the railway line (co-ordinate system) and that they are set in such a manner that the positions of their pointers are simultaneously (in the above sense) the same. Under these conditions we understand by the "time" of an event the reading (position of the hands) of that one of these clocks which is in the immediate vicinity (in space) of the event. In this manner a time-value is associated with every event which is essentially capable of observation.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XII: The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion 1.12.5 Let us now consider a seconds-clock which is permanently situated at the origin (x1=0) of K1.

t1=0 and t1=I are two successive ticks of this clock. The first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation give for these two ticks: t=0 and t'=1/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2).

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XI: The Lorentz Transformation 1.11.5 If in place of the law of transmission of light we had taken as our basis the tacit assumptions of the older mechanics as to the absolute character of times and lengths, then instead of the above we should have obtained the following equations:

x1 = x - vt y1 = y z1 = z t1 = t This system of equations is often termed the "Galilei transformation." The Galilei transformation can be obtained from the Lorentz transformation by substituting an infinitely large value for the velocity of light c in the latter transformation.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XII: The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion 1.12.1 Place a metre-rod in the x1-axis of K1 in such a manner that one end (the beginning) coincides with the point x1=0 whilst the other end (the end of the rod) coincides with the point x1=1. What is the length of the metre-rod relatively to the system K? In order to learn this, we need only ask where the beginning of the rod and the end of the rod lie with respect to K at a particular time t of the system K.

By means of the first equation of the Lorentz transformation the values of these two points at the time t = 0 can be shown to be x(beginning of rod)=0/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) x(end of rod)=1/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) the distance between the points being sqrt(1-v^2/c^2). But the metre-rod is moving with the velocity v relative to K. It therefore follows that the length of a rigid metre-rod moving in the direction of its length with a velocity v is sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) of a metre. The rigid rod is thus shorter when in motion than when at rest, and the more quickly it is moving, the shorter is the rod. For the velocity v=c we should have sqrt(1-v^2/c^2)=0 and for still greater velocities the square-root becomes imaginary. From this we conclude that in the theory of relativity the velocity c plays the part of a limiting velocity, which can neither be reached nor exceeded by any real body.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VIII: On the Idea of Time in Physics 1.08.3 After thinking the matter over for some time you then offer the following suggestion with which to test simultaneity.

By measuring along the rails, the connecting line AB should be measured up and an observer placed at the mid-point M of the distance AB. This observer should be supplied with an arrangement (e.g. two mirrors inclined at 900) which allows him visually to observe both places A and B at the same time. If the observer perceives the two flashes of lightning at the same time, then they are simultaneous.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section III: Space and Time in Classical Mechanics 1.03.2 It is not clear what is to be understood here by "position" and "space." I stand at the window of a railway carriage which is travelling uniformly, and drop a stone on the embankment, without throwing it. Then, disregarding the influence of the air resistance, I see the stone descend in a straight line. A pedestrian who observes the misdeed from the footpath notices that the stone falls to earth in a parabolic curve. I now ask: Do the "positions" traversed by the stone lie "in reality" on a straight line or on a parabola? Moreover, what is meant here by motion "in space"?

From the considerations of the previous section the answer is self-evident. In the first place we entirely shun the vague word "space," of which, we must honestly acknowledge, we cannot form the slightest conception, and we replace it by "motion relative to a practically rigid body of reference." The positions relative to the body of reference (railway carriage or embankment) have already been defined in detail in the preceding section. If instead of "body of reference" we insert "system of co-ordinates," which is a useful idea for mathematical description, we are in a position to say : The stone traverses a straight line relative to a system of co-ordinates rigidly attached to the carriage, but relative to a system of co-ordinates rigidly attached to the ground (embankment) it describes a parabola. With the aid of this example it is clearly seen that there is no such thing as an independently existing trajectory (lit. "path- curve"), but only a trajectory relative to a particular body of reference.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.5

From this consideration we see that it will be advantageous if, in the description of position, it should be possible by means of numerical measures to make ourselves independent of the existence of marked positions (possessing names) on the rigid body of reference. In the physics of measurement this is attained by the application of the Cartesian system of co-ordinates.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section I: Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions 1.01.3 It is not difficult to understand why, in spite of this, we feel constrained to call the propositions of geometry "true."

Geometrical ideas correspond to more or less exact objects in nature, and these last are undoubtedly the exclusive cause of the genesis of those ideas. Geometry ought to refrain from such a course, in order to give to its structure the largest possible logical unity. The practice, for example, of seeing in a "distance" two marked positions on a practically rigid body is something which is lodged deeply in our habit of thought. We are accustomed further to regard three points as being situated on a straight line, if their apparent positions can be made to coincide for observation with one eye, under suitable choice of our place of observation.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VIII: On the Idea of Time in Physics 1.08.4

I am very pleased with this suggestion, but for all that I cannot regard the matter as quite settled, because I feel constrained to raise the following objection: "Your definition would certainly be right, if only I knew that the light by means of which the observer at M perceives the lightning flashes travels along the length A--->M with the same velocity as along the length B--->M. But an examination of this supposition would only be possible if we already had at our disposal the means of measuring time. It would thus appear as though we were moving here in a logical circle."

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section III: Space and Time in Classical Mechanics 1.03.1

The purpose of mechanics is to describe how bodies change their position in space with "time." I should load my conscience with grave sins against the sacred spirit of lucidity were I to formulate the aims of mechanics in this way, without serious reflection and detailed explanations. Let us proceed to disclose these sins.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VII: The Apparent Incompatibility of the Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity 1.07.3 Of course we must refer the process of the propagation of light (and indeed every other process) to a rigid reference-body (co-ordinate system). As such a system let us again choose our embankment. We shall imagine the air above it to have been removed.

If a ray of light were sent along the embankment, we see from the above that the tip of the ray will be transmitted with the velocity c relative to the embankment. Now let us suppose that our railway carriage is again travelling along the railway lines with the velocity v, and that its direction is the same as that of the ray of light, but its velocity of course much less. Let us inquire about the velocity of propagation of the ray of light relative to the carriage. It is obvious that we can here apply the consideration of the previous section, since the ray of light plays the part of the man walking along relatively to the carriage. The velocity w of the man relative to the embankment is here replaced by the velocity of light relative to the embankment. w is the required velocity of light with respect to the carriage, and we have w=c-v. The velocity of propagation of a ray of light relative to the carriage thus comes cut smaller than c.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section IX: The Relativity of Simultaneity 1.09.2 When we say that the lightning strokes A and B are simultaneous with respect to be embankment, we mean: the rays of light emitted at the places A and B, where the lightning occurs, meet each other at the mid-point M of the length A ---> B of the embankment. But the events A and B also correspond to positions A and B on the train. Let M1 be the mid-point of the distance A ---> B on the travelling train. Just when the flashes (as judged from the embankment) of lightning occur, this point M1 naturally coincides with the point M but it moves towards the right in the diagram with the velocity v of the train.

If an observer sitting in the position M1 in the train did not possess this velocity, then he would remain permanently at M, and the light rays emitted by the flashes of lightning A and B would reach him simultaneously, i.e. they would meet just where he is situated. Now in reality (considered with reference to the railway embankment) he is hastening towards the beam of light coming from B, whilst he is riding on ahead of the beam of light coming from A. Hence the observer will see the beam of light emitted from B earlier than he will see that emitted from A. Observers who take the railway train as their reference-body must therefore come to the conclusion that the lightning flash B took place earlier than the lightning flash A. We thus arrive at the important result: Events which are simultaneous with reference to the embankment are not simultaneous with respect to the train, and vice versa (relativity of simultaneity). Every reference-body (co-ordinate system) has its own particular time; unless we are told the reference-body to which the statement of time refers, there is no meaning in a statement of the time of an event.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section V: The Principle of Relativity (in the restricted sense) 1.05.6 Now in virtue of its motion in an orbit round the sun, our earth is comparable with a railway carriage travelling with a velocity of about 30 kilometres per second.

If the principle of relativity were not valid we should therefore expect that the direction of motion of the earth at any moment would enter into the laws of nature, and also that physical systems in their behaviour would be dependent on the orientation in space with respect to the earth. For owing to the alteration in direction of the velocity of revolution of the earth in the course of a year, the earth cannot be at rest relative to the hypothetical system K0 throughout the whole year. However, the most careful observations have never revealed such anisotropic properties in terrestrial physical space, i.e. a physical non-equivalence of different directions. This is very powerful argument in favour of the principle of relativity.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section X: On the Relativity of the Conception of Distance 1.10.2 It is a different matter when the distance has to be judged from the railway line. Here the following method suggests itself.

If we call A1 and B1 the two points on the train whose distance apart is required, then both of these points are moving with the velocity v along the embankment. In the first place we require to determine the points A and B of the embankment which are just being passed by the two points A1 and B1 at a particular time t — judged from the embankment. These points A and B of the embankment can be determined by applying the definition of time given in Section 8. The distance between these points A and B is then measured by repeated application of the measuring-rod along the embankment.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section V: The Principle of Relativity (in the restricted sense) 1.05.1 In order to attain the greatest possible clearness, let us return to our example of the railway carriage supposed to be travelling uniformly. We call its motion a uniform translation ("uniform" because it is of constant velocity and direction, "translation" because although the carriage changes its position relative to the embankment yet it does not rotate in so doing). Let us imagine a raven flying through the air in such a manner that its motion, as observed from the embankment, is uniform and in a straight line.

If we were to observe the flying raven from the moving railway carriage. we should find that the motion of the raven would be one of different velocity and direction, but that it would still be uniform and in a straight line. Expressed in an abstract manner we may say: If a mass m is moving uniformly in a straight line with respect to a co-ordinate system K, then it will also be moving uniformly and in a straight line relative to a second co-ordinate system K1 provided that the latter is executing a uniform translatory motion with respect to K. In accordance with the discussion contained in the preceding section, it follows that: If K is a Galileian co-ordinate system. then every other co-ordinate system K' is a Galileian one, when, in relation to K, it is in a condition of uniform motion of translation. Relative to K1 the mechanical laws of Galilei-Newton hold good exactly as they do with respect to K.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VIII: On the Idea of Time in Physics 1.08.2 After some time perhaps the following answer would occur to you: "The significance of the statement is clear in itself and needs no further explanation; of course it would require some consideration if I were to be commissioned to determine by observations whether in the actual case the two events took place simultaneously or not." I cannot be satisfied with this answer for the following reason.

Supposing that as a result of ingenious considerations an able meteorologist were to discover that the lightning must always strike the places A and B simultaneously, then we should be faced with the task of testing whether or not this theoretical result is in accordance with the reality. We encounter the same difficulty with all physical statements in which the conception "simultaneous " plays a part. The concept does not exist for the physicist until he has the possibility of discovering whether or not it is fulfilled in an actual case. We thus require a definition of simultaneity such that this definition supplies us with the method by means of which, in the present case, he can decide by experiment whether or not both the lightning strikes occurred simultaneously. As long as this requirement is not satisfied, I allow myself to be deceived as a physicist (and of course the same applies if I am not a physicist), when I imagine that I am able to attach a meaning to the statement of simultaneity. (I would ask the reader not to proceed farther until he is fully convinced on this point.)

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VII: The Apparent Incompatibility of the Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity 1.07.5 In view of this dilemma there appears to be nothing else for it than to abandon either the principle of relativity or the simple law of the propagation of light in vacuo. Those of you who have carefully followed the preceding discussion are almost sure to expect that we should retain the principle of relativity, which appeals so convincingly to the intellect because it is so natural and simple.

The law of the propagation of light in vacuo would then have to be replaced by a more complicated law conformable to the principle of relativity. The development of theoretical physics shows, however, that we cannot pursue this course. The epoch-making theoretical investigations of H. A. Lorentz on the electrodynamical and optical phenomena connected with moving bodies show that experience in this domain leads conclusively to a theory of electromagnetic phenomena, of which the law of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo is a necessary consequence. Prominent theoretical physicists were therefore more inclined to reject the principle of relativity, in spite of the fact that no empirical data had been found which were contradictory to this principle.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VI: The Theorem of the Addition of Velocities Employed in Classical Mechanics 1.06.1 Let us suppose our old friend the railway carriage to be travelling along the rails with a constant velocity v, and that a man traverses the length of the carriage in the direction of travel with a velocity w. How quickly or, in other words, with what velocity W does the man advance relative to the embankment during the process?

The only possible answer seems to result from the following consideration: If the man were to stand still for a second, he would advance relative to the embankment through a distance v equal numerically to the velocity of the carriage. As a consequence of his walking, however, he traverses an additional distance w relative to the carriage, and hence also relative to the embankment, in this second, the distance w being numerically equal to the velocity with which he is walking. Thus in total he covers the distance W=v+w relative to the embankment in the second considered. We shall see later that this result, which expresses the theorem of the addition of velocities employed in classical mechanics, cannot be maintained; in other words, the law that we have just written down does not hold in reality. For the time being, however, we shall assume its correctness.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section I: Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions 1.01.2 Geometry sets out from certain conceptions such as "plane," "point," and "straight line," with which we are able to associate more or less definite ideas, and from certain simple propositions (axioms) which, in virtue of these ideas, we are inclined to accept as "true." Then, on the basis of a logical process, the justification of which we feel ourselves compelled to admit, all remaining propositions are shown to follow from those axioms, i.e. they are proven. A proposition is then correct ("true") when it has been derived in the recognised manner from the axioms.

The question of "truth" of the individual geometrical propositions is thus reduced to one of the "truth" of the axioms. Now it has long been known that the last question is not only unanswerable by the methods of geometry, but that it is in itself entirely without meaning. We cannot ask whether it is true that only one straight line goes through two points. We can only say that Euclidean geometry deals with things called "straight lines," to each of which is ascribed the property of being uniquely determined by two points situated on it. The concept "true" does not tally with the assertions of pure geometry, because by the word "true" we are eventually in the habit of designating always the correspondence with a "real" object; geometry, however, is not concerned with the relation of the ideas involved in it to objects of experience, but only with the logical connection of these ideas among themselves.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XI: The Lorentz Transformation 1.11.4 Obviously our problem can be exactly formulated in the following manner. What are the values x1, y1, z1, t1, of an event with respect to K1, when the magnitudes x, y, z, t, of the same event with respect to K are given?

The relations must be so chosen that the law of the transmission of light in vacuo is satisfied for one and the same ray of light (and of course for every ray) with respect to K and K1. For the relative orientation in space of the co-ordinate systems indicated in the diagram (Fig. 2), this problem is solved by means of the equations: x'=(x-vt)/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) y1=y z1=z t'=(t-vx/c^2)/sqrt(1-v^2/c^2) This system of equations is known as the "Lorentz transformation."

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XI: The Lorentz Transformation 1.11.1

The results of the last three sections show that the apparent incompatibility of the law of propagation of light with the principle of relativity (Section 7) has been derived by means of a consideration which borrowed two unjustifiable hypotheses from classical mechanics; these are as follows: (1) The time-interval (time) between two events is independent of the condition of motion of the body of reference. (2) The space-interval (distance) between two points of a rigid body is independent of the condition of motion of the body of reference.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section IV: The Galileian System of Co-ordinates 1.04.1 As is well known, the fundamental law of the mechanics of Galilei-Newton, which is known as the law of inertia, can be stated thus: A body removed sufficiently far from other bodies continues in a state of rest or of uniform motion in a straight line. This law not only says something about the motion of the bodies, but it also indicates the reference-bodies or systems of coordinates, permissible in mechanics, which can be used in mechanical description.

The visible fixed stars are bodies for which the law of inertia certainly holds to a high degree of approximation. Now if we use a system of co-ordinates which is rigidly attached to the earth, then, relative to this system, every fixed star describes a circle of immense radius in the course of an astronomical day, a result which is opposed to the statement of the law of inertia. So that if we adhere to this law we must refer these motions only to systems of coordinates relative to which the fixed stars do not move in a circle. A system of co-ordinates of which the state of motion is such that the law of inertia holds relative to it is called a "Galileian system of co-ordinates." The laws of the mechanics of Galilei-Newton can be regarded as valid only for a Galileian system of co-ordinates.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section VIII: On the Idea of Time in Physics 1.08.5 After further consideration you cast a somewhat disdainful glance at me — and rightly so — and you declare: "I maintain my previous definition nevertheless, because in reality it assumes absolutely nothing about light.

There is only one demand to be made of the definition of simultaneity, namely, that in every real case it must supply us with an empirical decision as to whether or not the conception that has to be defined is fulfilled. That my definition satisfies this demand is indisputable. That light requires the same time to traverse the path A--->M as for the path B--->M is in reality neither a supposition nor a hypothesis about the physical nature of light, but a stipulation which I can make of my own freewill in order to arrive at a definition of simultaneity."

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section V: The Principle of Relativity (in the restricted sense) 1.05.5 We now proceed to the second argument, to which, moreover, we shall return later. If the principle of relativity (in the restricted sense) does not hold, then the Galileian co-ordinate systems K, K1, K2, etc., which are moving uniformly relative to each other, will not be equivalent for the description of natural phenomena. In this case we should be constrained to believe that natural laws are capable of being formulated in a particularly simple manner, and of course only on condition that, from amongst all possible Galileian co-ordinate systems, we should have chosen one (K0) of a particular state of motion as our body of reference.

We should then be justified (because of its merits for the description of natural phenomena) in calling this system "absolutely at rest," and all other Galileian systems K "in motion." If, for instance, our embankment were the system K0 then our railway carriage would be a system K, relative to which less simple laws would hold than with respect to K0. This diminished simplicity would be due to the fact that the carriage K would be in motion (i.e."really") with respect to K0. In the general laws of nature which have been formulated with reference to K, the magnitude and direction of the velocity of the carriage would necessarily play a part. We should expect, for instance, that the note emitted by an organpipe placed with its axis parallel to the direction of travel would be different from that emitted if the axis of the pipe were placed perpendicular to this direction.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section II: The System of Co-ordinates 1.02.8

We thus obtain the following result: Every description of events in space involves the use of a rigid body to which such events have to be referred. The resulting relationship takes for granted that the laws of Euclidean geometry hold for "distances;" the "distance" being represented physically by means of the convention of two marks on a rigid body.

Relativity: The Special and General Theory by Albert Einstein Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity Section XI: The Lorentz Transformation 1.11.3 Before we deal with this, we shall introduce the following incidental consideration. Up to the present we have only considered events taking place along the embankment, which had mathematically to assume the function of a straight line. In the manner indicated in Section 2 we can imagine this reference-body supplemented laterally and in a vertical direction by means of a framework of rods, so that an event which takes place anywhere can be localised with reference to this framework. Similarly, we can imagine the train travelling with the velocity v to be continued across the whole of space, so that every event, no matter how far off it may be, could also be localised with respect to the second framework.

Without committing any fundamental error, we can disregard the fact that in reality these frameworks would continually interfere with each other, owing to the impenetrability of solid bodies. In every such framework we imagine three surfaces perpendicular to each other marked out, and designated as "co-ordinate planes" ("co-ordinate system"). A co-ordinate system K then corresponds to the embankment, and a co-ordinate system K' to the train. An event, wherever it may have taken place, would be fixed in space with respect to K by the three perpendiculars x, y, z on the co-ordinate planes, and with regard to time by a time value t. Relative to K1, the same event would be fixed in respect of space and time by corresponding values x1, y1, z1, t1, which of course are not identical with x, y, z, t. It has already been set forth in detail how these magnitudes are to be regarded as results of physical measurements.


Kaugnay na mga set ng pag-aaral

chapter 16, Advertising Exam 3 - Kwon, Chapters 14-16 Quiz Questions, advertising, ADV EXAM 3, Advertising Chapter 11 LS and Quiz, advertising, ADV 205 Exam 2

View Set

Professional Home Inspector Exam NHIE / TREC #2

View Set

Pennsylvania State Health and Life Insurance Exam

View Set

Combination: Alquimista Questions 68-81

View Set